
axiom of choice 31
the representation “2 1 0 1,” and it is true that
.
See also
BASE OF A NUMBER SYSTEM
.
axiom (postulate) A statement whose truth is
deemed self-evident or to be accepted without proof is
called an axiom. The name comes from the Greek
word axioma for “worth” or “quality.” The alterna-
tive name “postulate” comes from postulatum, Latin
for “a thing demanded.”
One of the great achievements of the great Greek
geometer E
UCLID
and his contemporaries of around 300
B
.
C
.
E
. was to recognize that not every statement in
mathematics can be proved: certain terms remain unde-
fined, and basic rules (postulates) about their relation-
ships must simply be accepted as true. One must
develop a mathematical theory with a “big bang,” as it
were, by simply listing a starting set of assumptions.
From there, using the basic laws of reasoning, one then
establishes and proves further statements, or
THEO
-
REM
s, about the system.
For example, in a systematic study of E
UCLIDEAN
GEOMETRY
, the terms point, line, and plane are unde-
fined, and one begins a systematic study of the subject
by studying a list of basic axioms that tells us how
these quantities are meant to interrelate. (One axiom
of Euclidean geometry, for instance, asserts that
between any two points one can draw a line.) All the
results presented in a typical high-school text on geom-
etry, for example, are logical consequences of just five
principal assumptions.
In
SET THEORY
, the terms set and element of a set
are undefined. However, rules are given that define the
equality of two sets, that guarantee the existence of cer-
tain sets, and establish the means of constructing new
sets from old ones. In
NUMBER THEORY
, P
EANO
’
S POS
-
TULATES
provide a logical foundation to the theory of
numbers and arithmetic.
A statement in a mathematical system that appears
true, but has not yet been proved, is called a conjecture.
See also
DEDUCTIVE
/
INDUCTIVE REASONING
; E
RNST
F
RIEDRICH
F
ERDINAND
Z
ERMELO
.
axiom of choice First formulated by German mathe-
matician E
RNST
F
RIEDRICH
F
ERDINAND
Z
ERMELO
(1871–1953), the axiom of choice is a basic principle of
SET THEORY
that states that from any given collection C
of nonempty sets, it is possible to construct a set Sthat
contains one element from each of the sets in C. The set S
is called a “choice set” for C. For example, if Crepre-
sents the three sets {1,2,3}, {2,4,6,8,…}, and {5}, then
S= {1,6,5} is a choice set for C. So too is the set S= {2,5}.
The axiom of choice has been considered counter-
intuitive when interpreted on a practical level: although
it is possible to select one element from each of a finite
collection of sets in a finite amount of time, it is physi-
cally impossible to accomplish the same feat when pre-
sented with an infinite collection of sets. The existence
of a choice set is not “constructive,” as it were, and use
of the axiom is viewed by mathematicians, even today,
with suspicion. In 1938 Austrian mathematician K
URT
G
ÖDEL
proved, however, that no contradiction would
ever arise when the axiom of choice is used in conjunc-
tion with other standard axioms of set theory.
Zermelo formulated the axiom to prove that every
ordered set can be well-ordered. The axiom of choice
also proves (and in fact is equivalent to) the trichotomy
law, which states that for any pair of
REAL NUMBERS
a
and b, precisely one of the following holds:
i. a> b
ii. a< b
iii. a= b
Although this statement, on one level, appears obvious,
its validity is fundamental to the workings of the real
numbers and so needs to be properly understood.
See also
WELL
-
ORDERED SET
.
23
213
203
213
210
32 10
×
+×
+×
+×
=