
event, given that the number 1,849 is 43 squared. He
also observed that all those born in the year 1892
would enjoy a similar coincidence in the year 1936,
and those born in 1980 one in the year 2025. (The
number 2,025 is 45 squared.)
De Morgan died in London, England, on March
18, 1871.
See also D
E
M
ORGAN
’
SLAWS
.
De Morgan’s laws If Aand Bare two subsets of a
universal set, and A′and B′denote their complements,
then the following two identities, known as De Mor-
gan’s laws, hold:
(A∩B)′= A′∪B′
(A∪B)′ =A′∩B′
These identities can be used to convert any intersection
of sets into a union of sets, or vice versa.
These laws can be seen to hold true with the aid of
a V
ENN DIAGRAM
(by shading the region outside the
intersection or the union of the two sets), or by a formal
SET THEORY
argument. For instance, to prove the first
law, one must establish that any element that belongs to
(A∩B)′also belongs to A′∪B′, and vice versa. This can
be done as follows:
If x∈(A∩B)′, then x∉A∩B, meaning that x
does not belong to both Aand B. Conse-
quently, xbelongs to at least one complement
A′or B′, and so x∈A′∪B′.
Conversely, if y∈A′∪B′, then ydoes not
belong to one (or both) of Aand B. Conse-
quently, yis not an element of A∩B, and so
y ∈(A∩B)′.
The second law can be proved similarly.
De Morgan’s laws can be extended to the intersec-
tion or union of more than two sets. We have:
(A∩B∩C∩…∩Z)′= A∪B′∪C′∪…∪Z′
(A∪B∪C∪…∪Z)′= A′∩B′∩C′∩…∩Z′
When a set Ais interpreted as “the set of all instances
in which a claim pis true,” and B“the set of all
instances in which a claim qis true,” then De Morgan’s
laws in set theory translate to the following two identi-
ties in
FORMAL LOGIC
:
¬
(pq) = (
¬
p)∨(
¬
q)
¬
(p∨q) = (
¬
p)(
¬
q)
A
TRUTH TABLE
establishes that these corresponding
pairs of compound statements are logically equivalent.
These equivalences are also called De Morgan’s laws.
The formulae presented above were proposed in
1847 by Indian-born British mathematician and logi-
cian A
UGUSTUS
D
E
M
ORGAN
(1806–71).
denumerable (enumerable, numerable) A
COUNT
-
ABLE
infinite set is said to be denumerable. Thus a
denumerable set is any infinite set whose elements can
be placed in a list akin to the list of natural numbers 1,
2, 3, … The first
DIAGONAL ARGUMENT
shows that the
set of
RATIONAL NUMBERS
is denumerable. The diago-
nal argument of the second kind establishes that the set
of
REAL NUMBERS
is not. In some definite sense then,
the set of real numbers is a “larger” infinite set than
the infinite set of rationals. A denumerable set is said to
have
CARDINALITY
ℵ0. Every infinite set contains a
denumerable subset. This can be established as follows:
Suppose Xis an infinite set. Let x1be any ele-
ment of X. Since Xis infinite, this is not the
only element of X. Let x2be another element
of X. Since Xis infinite, these are not the only
two elements of X. Let x3be another element
of X. Thus continuing this way produces a list
of elements of X: x1, x2, x3, … This list repre-
sents a denumerable subset of X.
One can legitimately say, then, that a denumerable set
is the “smallest” type of infinite set. That is, ℵ0is the
“smallest” transfinite cardinal number.
See also
CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS
.
derivative See
DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS
.
Desargues, Girard (1591–1661) French Geometry,
Engineering Born on February 21, 1591, in Lyon,
France, mathematician Girard Desargues is considered
the founder of
PROJECTIVE GEOMETRY
, an innovative,
non-Greek, approach to geometry. His highly original
and famous 1639 text Brouillon project d’une atteinte
aux evenemens des recontres du cone avec un plan
∨
∨
Desargues, Girard 123