real number
1 Definition
There are several equivalent definitions of real number, all in common use. We give one definition in detail and mention the other ones.
A Cauchy sequence of rational numbers is a sequence
of rational numbers with the property that, for every rational number , there exists a natural number
such that, for all natural numbers , the absolute value
satisfies .
The set of real numbers is the set of equivalence classes of Cauchy sequences of rational numbers, under the equivalence relation if the interleave sequence of the two sequences is itself a Cauchy sequence.The real numbers form a ring, with addition
and multiplication defined by
- •
- •
There is an ordering relation on , defined by if either or there exists a natural number such that for all . This definition is well-defined and does not depend on the choice of Cauchy sequences used to represent the equivalence classes.
One can prove that the real numbers form an ordered field and that they satisfy the Dedekind completeness property (also known as the least upper bound property): For every nonempty subset , if has an upper bound then has a lowest upper bound. It is also true that every ordered field with the least upper bound property is isomorphic to the real numbers.
Alternative definitions of the set of real numbers include:
- 1.
Equivalence classes of decimal sequences (sequences consisting of natural numbers between 0 and 9, and a single decimal point), where two decimal sequences are equivalent if they are identical, or if one has an infinite
tail of 9’s, the other has an infinite tail of 0’s, and the leading portion of the first sequence is one lower than the leading portion of the second.
- 2.
Dedekind cuts
of rational numbers (that is, subsets of with the property that, if and , then ).
- 3.
The real numbers can also be defined as the unique (up to isomorphism
) ordered field satisfying the least upper bound property, after one has proved that such a field exists and is unique up to isomorphism.
2 Completeness
The main reason for introducing the reals is that the reals contain all limits.More technically, the reals are complete (in the sense of metric spaces oruniform spaces, which is a different sense than the Dedekind completeness ofthe order in the previous section
). This means the following:
A sequence of real numbers is called a Cauchy sequence if for anythere exists an integer (possibly depending on ) such that thedistance is less than provided that and areboth greater than . In otherwords, a sequence is a Cauchy sequence if its elements eventually comeand remain arbitrarily close to each other.
A sequence converges to the limit if for any there exists an integer (possibly depending on ) such that thedistance is less than provided that is greaterthan . In other words, a sequence has limit if its elements eventuallycome and remain arbitrarily close to .
It is easy to see that every convergent sequence is a Cauchy sequence. Now theimportant fact about the real numbers is that the converse is true:
Every Cauchy sequence of real numbers is convergent
.
That is, the reals are complete.
Note that the rationals are not complete. For example, the sequence , ,, , , , is Cauchy but it does notconverge to a rational number. (In the real numbers, in contrast, it convergesto the square root of .)
The existence of limits of Cauchy sequences is what makes calculus work and isof great practical use. The standard numerical test to determine if a sequencehas a limit is to test if it is a Cauchy sequence, as the limit is typicallynot known in advance.
For example the standard series of the exponential function
converges to a real number because for every the sums
can be made arbitrarily small by choosing sufficiently large. This provesthat the sequence is Cauchy, so we know that the sequence converges even if wedon’t know ahead of time what the limit is.
3 “The complete ordered field”
The real numbers are often described as “the complete ordered field,” a phrasethat can be interpreted in several ways.
First, an order can be lattice complete. It’s easy to see that no ordered fieldcan be lattice complete, because it can have no largest element (given anyelement , is larger), so this is not the sense that is meant.
Additionally, an order can be Dedekind-complete, as defined in the Definitions section. The uniqueness result at the end of that section justifies using theword “the” in the phrase “complete ordered field” when this is the sense of“complete” that is meant. This sense of completeness is most closely related to the construction of the reals from Dedekind cuts, since that constructionstarts from an ordered field (the rationals) and then forms the Dedekind-completion of it in a standard way.
These two notions of completeness ignore the field structure. However, anordered group (and a field is a group under the operations
of addition andsubtraction
) defines a uniform structure, and uniform structures have a notionof completeness (topology
); the description in the Completeness section aboveis a special case. (We refer to the notion of completeness in uniform spacesrather than the related and better known notion for metric spaces, since thedefinition of metric space relies on already having a characterisation of thereal numbers.) It is not true that is the only uniformly completeorderedfield, but it is the only uniformly complete Archimedean field, and indeed oneoften hears the phrase “complete Archimedean field” instead of “completeordered field.” Since it can be proved that any uniformly complete Archimedeanfield must also be Dedekind complete (and vice versa, of course), thisjustifies using “the” in the phrase “the complete Archimedean field.” Thissense of completeness is most closely related to the construction of the realsfrom Cauchy sequences (the construction carried out in full in this article),since it starts with an Archimedean field (the rationals) and forms the uniformcompletion of it in a standard way.
But the original use of the phrase “complete Archimedean field” was by DavidHilbert, who meant still something else by it. He meant that the real numbersform the largest Archimedean field in the sense that every other Archimedeanfield is a subfield of . Thus is “complete” in thesense that nothingfurther can be added to it without making it no longer an Archimedean field.This sense of completeness is most closely related to the construction of thereals from surreal numbers
, since that construction starts with a proper class
that contains every ordered field (the surreals) and then selects from it thelargest Archimedean
subfield.
This article contains material from the http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Real_numbersWikipedia article on Real numbers which is incorporated herein under the terms of the http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Wikipedia:Text_of_the_GNU_Free_Documentation_LicenseGNU Free Documentation License.