请输入您要查询的字词:

 

单词 1121TheAlgebraicStructureOfDedekindReals
释义

11.2.1 The algebraic structure of Dedekind reals


The construction of the algebraic and order-theoretic structureMathworldPlanetmath of Dedekind reals proceedsas usual in intuitionistic logicMathworldPlanetmath. Rather than dwelling on details we point out thedifferencesPlanetmathPlanetmath between the classical and intuitionistic setup. Writing Lx and Ux forthe lower and upper cut of a real number x:𝖽, we define addition as

Lx+y(q):(r,s:).Lx(r)Ly(s)q=r+s,
Ux+y(q):(r,s:).Ux(r)Uy(s)q=r+s,

and the additive inverse by

L-x(q):(r:).Ux(r)q=-r,
U-x(q):(r:).Lx(r)q=-r.

With these operationsMathworldPlanetmath (𝖽,0,+,-) is an abelian groupMathworldPlanetmath. Multiplication is a bitmore cumbersome:

Lxy(q):(a,b,c,d:).Lx(a)Ux(b)Ly(c)Uy(d)q<min(ac,ad,bc,bd),
Uxy(q):(a,b,c,d:).Lx(a)Ux(b)Ly(c)Uy(d)max(ac,ad,bc,bd)<q.

These formulasMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmath are related to multiplication of intervals in interval arithmetic, whereintervals [a,b] and [c,d] with rational endpoints multiply to the interval

[a,b][c,d]=[min(ac,ad,bc,bd),max(ac,ad,bc,bd)].

For instance, the formula for the lower cut can be read as saying that q<xywhen there are intervals [a,b] and [c,d] containing x and y, respectively, suchthat q is to the left of [a,b][c,d]. It is generally useful to think of aninterval [a,b] such that Lx(a) and Ux(b) as an approximation of x, see\\autorefex:RD-interval-arithmetic.

We now have a commutative ring with unit(𝖽,0,1,+,-,). To treatmultiplicative inversesMathworldPlanetmath, we must first introduce order. Define and < as

(xy) :(q:).Lx(q)Ly(q),
(x<y) :(q:).Ux(q)Ly(q).
Lemma 11.2.1.

For all x:Rd and q:Q, Lx(q)(q<x) and Ux(q)(x<q).

Proof.

If Lx(q) then by roundedness there merely is r>q such that Lx(r), and sinceUq(r) it follows that q<x. Conversely, if q<x then there is r: suchthat Uq(r) and Lx(r), hence Lx(q) because Lx is a lower set. The other halfof the proof is symmetricPlanetmathPlanetmath.∎

The relationMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmath is a partial orderMathworldPlanetmath, and < is transitiveMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath and irreflexiveMathworldPlanetmath. Linearity

(x<y)(yx)

is valid if we assume excluded middle, but without it we get weak linearity

(x<y)(x<z)(z<y).(11.2.2)

At first sight it might not be clear what (11.2.2) has to do withlinear order. But if we take xu-ϵ and yu+ϵ forϵ>0, then we get

(u-ϵ<z)(z<u+ϵ).

This is linearity “up to a small numerical error”, i.e., since it is unreasonable toexpect that we can actually compute with infiniteMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmath precision, we should not be surprisedthat we can decide < only up to whatever finite precision we have computed.

To see that (11.2.2) holds, suppose x<y. Then there merely exists q: such that Ux(q) andLy(q). By roundedness there merely exist r,s: such that r<q<s, Ux(r)and Ly(s). Then, by locatedness Lz(r) or Uz(s). In the first case we get x<zand in the second z<y.

Classically, multiplicative inverses exist for all numbers which are different from zero.However, without excluded middle, a stronger condition is required. Say that x,y:𝖽are apartfrom each other, written x#y, when (x<y)(y<x):

(x#y):(x<y)(y<x).

If x#y, then ¬(x=y).The converse is true if we assume excluded middle, but is not provable constructively.Indeed, if ¬(x=y) implies x#y, then a little bit of excluded middle follows; see \\autorefex:reals-apart-neq-MP.

Theorem 11.2.3.

A real is invertiblePlanetmathPlanetmath if, and only if, it is apart from 0.

Remark 11.2.4.

We observe that a real is invertible if, and only if, it is merelyinvertible. Indeed, the same is true in any ring, since a ring is a set, andmultiplicative inverses are unique if they exist. See the discussionfollowing \\autorefcor:UC.

Proof.

Suppose xy=1. Then there merely exist a,b,c,d: such thata<x<b, c<y<d and 0<min(ac,ad,bc,bd). From 0<ac and 0<bc it followsthat a, b, and c are either all positive or all negative.Hence either 0<a<x or x<b<0, so that x#0.

Conversely, if x#0 then

Lx-1(q):(r:).Ux(r)((0<rqr<1)(r<01<qr))
Ux-1(q):(r:).Lx(r)((0<rqr>1)(r<01>qr))

defines the desired inverseMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath. Indeed, Lx-1 and Ux-1 are inhabited becausex#0.∎

The archimedean principle can be stated in several ways. We find it most illuminating in theform which says that is dense in 𝖽.

Theorem 11.2.5 (Archimedean principle for Rd).

For all x,y:Rd if x<y then there merely exists q:Q such thatx<q<y.

Proof.

By definition of <.∎

Before tackling completeness of Dedekind reals, let us state precisely what algebraicstructurePlanetmathPlanetmath they possess. In the following definition we are not aiming at a minimalPlanetmathPlanetmathaxiomatization, but rather at a useful amount of structure and properties.

Definition 11.2.6.

An ordered fieldis a set F together withconstants 0, 1, operations +, -, , min, max, and mere relations, <, # such that:

  1. 1.

    (F,0,1,+,-,) is a commutative ring with unit;

  2. 2.

    x:F is invertible if, and only if, x#0;

  3. 3.

    (F,,min,max) is a latticeMathworldPlanetmath;

  4. 4.

    the strict order < is transitive, irreflexive,and weakly linear (x<yx<zz<y);

  5. 5.

    apartness # is irreflexive, symmetric and cotransitive (x#yx#zy#z);

  6. 6.

    for all x,y,z:F:

    xy¬(y<x),x<yzx<z,
    x#y(x<y)(y<x),xy<zx<z,
    xyx+zy+z,xy0zxzyz,
    x<yx+z<y+z,0<z(x<yxz<yz),
    0<x+y0<x0<y,0<1.

Every such field has a canonical embeddingMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath QF. An ordered field isarchimedeanPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathwhen for all x,y:F, if x<y then there merely exists q:Q such that x<q<y.

Theorem 11.2.7.

The Dedekind reals form an ordered archimedean field.

Proof.

We omit the proof in the hope that what we have demonstrated so far makes the theoremplausible.∎

随便看

 

数学辞典收录了18232条数学词条,基本涵盖了常用数学知识及数学英语单词词组的翻译及用法,是数学学习的有利工具。

 

Copyright © 2000-2023 Newdu.com.com All Rights Reserved
更新时间:2025/5/4 15:59:53