请输入您要查询的字词:

 

单词 1123DedekindRealsAreDedekindComplete
释义

11.2.3 Dedekind reals are Dedekind complete


We obtained 𝖽 as the type of Dedekind cutsMathworldPlanetmath on . But we could have instead startedwith any archimedeanPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath ordered field F and constructed Dedekind cuts on F. These wouldagain form an archimedean ordered field F¯, the Dedekind completion of F,with F contained as a subfieldMathworldPlanetmath. What happens if we apply this construction to𝖽, do we get even more real numbers? The answer is negative. In fact, we shall prove astronger result: 𝖽 is final.

Say that an ordered field F is admissible for Ωwhen the strict order< on F is a map <:FFΩ.

Theorem 11.2.1.

Every archimedean ordered field which is admissible for Ω is a subfield of Rd.

Proof.

Let F be an archimedean ordered field. For every x:F define L,U:Ω by

Lx(q):(q<x)  and  Ux(q):(x<q).

(We have just used the assumptionPlanetmathPlanetmath that F is admissible for Ω.)Then (Lx,Ux) is a Dedekind cut. Indeed, the cuts are inhabited and rounded becauseF is archimedean and < is transitiveMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath, disjoint because < is irreflexiveMathworldPlanetmath, andlocated because < is a weak linear order. Let e:F𝖽 be the map e(x):(Lx,Ux).

We claim that e is a field embeddingPlanetmathPlanetmath which preserves and reflects the order. First ofall, notice that e(q)=q for a rational number q. Next we have the equivalences,for all x,y:F,

x<y((q:).x<q<y)((q:).Ux(q)Ly(q))e(x)<e(y),

so e indeed preserves and reflects the order. That e(x+y)=e(x)+e(y) holdsbecause, for all q:,

q<x+y(r,s:).r<xs<yq=r+s.

The implicationMathworldPlanetmath from right to left is obvious. For the other direction, if q<x+y then there merely exists r: such that q-y<r<x, and by taking s:q-r we get the desired r and s. We leave preservation of multiplicationPlanetmathPlanetmath by e asan exercise.∎

To establish that the Dedekind cuts on 𝖽 do not give us anything new, we need just onemore lemma.

Lemma 11.2.2.

If F is admissible for Ω then so is its Dedekind completion.

Proof.

Let F¯ be the Dedekind completion of F. The strict order on F¯ isdefined by

((L,U)<(L,U)):(q:).U(q)L(q).

Since U(q) and L(q) are elements of Ω, the lemma holds as long as Ωis closed under conjunctionsMathworldPlanetmath and countableMathworldPlanetmath existentials, which we assumed from the outset.∎

Corollary 11.2.3.

The Dedekind reals are Dedekind complete: for every real-valued Dedekind cut (L,U)there is a unique x:Rd such that L(y)=(y<x) and U(y)=(x<y) for all y:Rd.

Proof.

By \\autoreflem:cuts-preserve-admissibility the Dedekind completion ¯𝖽 of 𝖽is admissible for Ω, so by \\autorefRD-final-field we have an embedding ¯𝖽𝖽, as well as an embedding 𝖽¯𝖽. But these embeddings must beisomorphismsPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath, because their compositions are order-preserving field homomorphisms whichfix the dense subfield , which means that they are the identityPlanetmathPlanetmath. The corollary nowfollows immediately from the fact that ¯𝖽𝖽 is an isomorphism.∎

随便看

 

数学辞典收录了18232条数学词条,基本涵盖了常用数学知识及数学英语单词词组的翻译及用法,是数学学习的有利工具。

 

Copyright © 2000-2023 Newdu.com.com All Rights Reserved
更新时间:2025/5/4 16:09:30