请输入您要查询的字词:

 

单词 65Suspensions
释义

6.5 Suspensions


The suspension of a type A is the universalPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath way of making the points of A into paths (and hence the paths in A into 2-paths, and so on).It is a type ΣA defined by the following generatorsPlanetmathPlanetmath:11There is an unfortunate clash of notation with dependent pair types, which of course are also written with a Σ.However, context usually disambiguates.

  • a point 𝖭:ΣA,

  • a point 𝖲:ΣA, and

  • a function 𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽:A(𝖭=ΣA𝖲).

The names are intended to suggest a “globe” of sorts, with a north pole, a south pole, and an A’s worth of meridiansfrom one to the other.Indeed, as we will see, if A=𝕊1, then its suspension is equivalentMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath to the surface of an ordinary sphere, 𝕊2.

The recursion principle for ΣA says that given a type B together with

  • points n,s:B and

  • a function m:A(n=s),

we have a function f:ΣAB such that f(𝖭)n and f(𝖲)s, and for all a:A we have f(𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(a))=m(a).Similarly, the inductionMathworldPlanetmath principle says that given P:ΣA𝒰 together with

  • a point n:P(𝖭),

  • a point s:P(𝖲), and

  • for each a:A, a path m(a):n=𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(a)Ps,

there exists a function f:(x:ΣA)P(x) such that f(𝖭)n and f(𝖲)s and for each a:A we have 𝖺𝗉𝖽f(𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(a))=m(a).

Our first observation about suspension is that it gives another way to define the circle.

Lemma 6.5.1.

Σ𝟐𝕊1.

Proof.

Define f:Σ𝟐𝕊1 by recursion such that f(𝖭):𝖻𝖺𝗌𝖾 and f(𝖲):𝖻𝖺𝗌𝖾, while f(𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(0𝟐)):=𝗅𝗈𝗈𝗉 but f(𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(1𝟐)):=𝗋𝖾𝖿𝗅𝖻𝖺𝗌𝖾.Define g:𝕊1Σ𝟐 by recursion such that g(𝖻𝖺𝗌𝖾):𝖭 and g(𝗅𝗈𝗈𝗉):=𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(0𝟐)\\centerdot𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(1𝟐)-1.We now show that f and g are quasi-inverses.

First we show by induction that g(f(x))=x for all x:Σ𝟐.If x𝖭, then g(f(𝖭))g(𝖻𝖺𝗌𝖾)𝖭, so we have 𝗋𝖾𝖿𝗅𝖭:g(f(𝖭))=𝖭.If x𝖲, then g(f(𝖲))g(𝖻𝖺𝗌𝖾)𝖭, and we choose the equality 𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(1𝟐):g(f(𝖲))=𝖲.It remains to show that for any y:𝟐, these equalities are preserved as x varies along 𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(y), which is to say that when 𝗋𝖾𝖿𝗅𝖭 is transported along 𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(y) it yields 𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(1𝟐).By transport in path spaces and pulled back fibrations, this means we are to show that

g(f(𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(y)))-1\\centerdot𝗋𝖾𝖿𝗅𝖭\\centerdot𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(y)=𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(1𝟐).

Of course, we may cancel 𝗋𝖾𝖿𝗅𝖭.Now by 𝟐-induction, we may assume either y0𝟐 or y1𝟐.If y0𝟐, then we have

g(f(𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(0𝟐)))-1\\centerdot𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(0𝟐)=g(𝗅𝗈𝗈𝗉)-1\\centerdot𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(0𝟐)
=(𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(0𝟐)\\centerdot𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(1𝟐)-1)-1\\centerdot𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(0𝟐)
=𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(1𝟐)\\centerdot𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(0𝟐)-1\\centerdot𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(0𝟐)
=𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(1𝟐)

while if y1𝟐, then we have

g(f(𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(1𝟐)))-1\\centerdot𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(1𝟐)=g(𝗋𝖾𝖿𝗅𝖻𝖺𝗌𝖾)-1\\centerdot𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(1𝟐)
=𝗋𝖾𝖿𝗅𝖭-1\\centerdot𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(1𝟐)
=𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(1𝟐).

Thus, for all x:Σ𝟐, we have g(f(x))=x.

Now we show by induction that f(g(x))=x for all x:𝕊1.If x𝖻𝖺𝗌𝖾, then f(g(𝖻𝖺𝗌𝖾))f(𝖭)𝖻𝖺𝗌𝖾, so we have 𝗋𝖾𝖿𝗅𝖻𝖺𝗌𝖾:f(g(𝖻𝖺𝗌𝖾))=𝖻𝖺𝗌𝖾.It remains to show that this equality is preserved as x varies along 𝗅𝗈𝗈𝗉, which is to say that it is transported along 𝗅𝗈𝗈𝗉 to itself.Again, by transport in path spaces and pulled back fibrations, this means to show that

f(g(𝗅𝗈𝗈𝗉))-1\\centerdot𝗋𝖾𝖿𝗅𝖻𝖺𝗌𝖾\\centerdot𝗅𝗈𝗈𝗉=𝗋𝖾𝖿𝗅𝖻𝖺𝗌𝖾.

However, we have

f(g(𝗅𝗈𝗈𝗉))=f(𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(0𝟐)\\centerdot𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(1𝟐)-1)
=f(𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(0𝟐))\\centerdotf(𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(1𝟐))-1
=𝗅𝗈𝗈𝗉\\centerdot𝗋𝖾𝖿𝗅𝖻𝖺𝗌𝖾

so this follows easily.∎

Topologically, the two-point space 𝟐 is also known as the 0-dimensional sphere, 𝕊0.(For instance, it is the space of points at distance 1 from the origin in 1, just as the topological 1-sphere is the space of points at distance 1 from the origin in 2.)Thus, Lemma 6.5.1 (http://planetmath.org/65suspensions#Thmprelem1) can be phrased suggestively as Σ𝕊0𝕊1.In fact, this pattern continues: we can define all the spheres inductively by

𝕊0:𝟐  and  𝕊n+1:Σ𝕊n.(6.5.2)

We can even start one dimensionMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmath lower by defining 𝕊-1:𝟎, and observe that Σ𝟎𝟐.

To prove carefully that this agrees with the definition of 𝕊n from the previous sectionPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath would require making the latter more explicit.However, we can show that the recursive definition has the same universal property that we would expect the other one to have.If (A,a0) and (B,b0) are pointed types (with basepoints often left implicit), let 𝖬𝖺𝗉*(A,B) denote the type of based maps:

𝖬𝖺𝗉*(A,B):f:AB(f(a0)=b0).

Note that any type A gives rise to a pointed type A+:A+𝟏 with basepoint 𝗂𝗇𝗋(); this is called adjoining a disjoint basepoint.

Lemma 6.5.3.

For a type A and a pointed type (B,b0), we have

𝖬𝖺𝗉*(A+,B)(AB)

Note that on the right we have the ordinary type of unbased functions from A to B.

Proof.

From left to right, given f:A+B with p:f(𝗂𝗇𝗋())=b0, we have f𝗂𝗇𝗅:AB.And from right to left, given g:AB we define g:A+B by g(𝗂𝗇𝗅(a)):g(a) and g(𝗂𝗇𝗋(u)):b0.We leave it to the reader to show that these are quasi-inverse operationsMathworldPlanetmath.∎

In particular, note that 𝟐𝟏+.Thus, for any pointed type B we have

𝖬𝖺𝗉*(𝟐,B)(𝟏B)B.

Now recall that the loop spaceMathworldPlanetmath operation Ω acts on pointed types, with definition Ω(A,a0):(a0=Aa0,𝗋𝖾𝖿𝗅a0).We can also make the suspension Σ act on pointed types, by Σ(A,a0):(ΣA,𝖭).

Lemma 6.5.4.

For pointed types (A,a0) and (B,b0) we have

𝖬𝖺𝗉*(ΣA,B)𝖬𝖺𝗉*(A,ΩB).
Proof.

From left to right, given f:ΣAB with p:f(𝖭)=b0, we define g:AΩB by

g(a):p-1\\centerdotf(𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(a)\\centerdot𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(a0)-1)\\centerdotp.

Then we have

g(a0)p-1\\centerdotf(𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(a0)\\centerdot𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(a0)-1)\\centerdotp
=p-1\\centerdotf(𝗋𝖾𝖿𝗅𝖭)\\centerdotp
=p-1\\centerdotp
=𝗋𝖾𝖿𝗅b0.

Thus, denoting this path by q:g(a0)=𝗋𝖾𝖿𝗅b0, we have (g,q):𝖬𝖺𝗉*(A,ΩB).

On the other hand, from right to left, given g:AΩB and q:g(a0)=𝗋𝖾𝖿𝗅b0, we define f:ΣAB by Σ-recursion, such that f(𝖭):b0 and f(𝖲):b0 and

f(𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(a)):=g(a).

Then we can simply take p to be 𝗋𝖾𝖿𝗅b0:f(𝖭)=b0.

Now given (f,p), by passing back and forth we obtain (f,p) where f is defined by f(𝖭)b0 and f(𝖲)b0 and

f(𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(a))=p-1\\centerdotf(𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(a)\\centerdot𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(a0)-1)\\centerdotp,

while p𝗋𝖾𝖿𝗅b0.To show f=f, by function extensionality it suffices to show f(x)=f(x) for all x:ΣA, so we can use the induction principle of suspension.First, we have

f(𝖭)=𝑝b0f(𝖭).(6.5.5)

Second, we have

\\includegraphics

HoTT_fig_6.5.1.png

And thirdly, as x varies along 𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(a) we must show that the following diagram of paths commutes (invoking the definition of f(𝗆𝖾𝗋𝗂𝖽(a))):

\\includegraphics

HoTT_fig_6.5.2.png

This is clear.Thus, to show that (f,p)=(f,p), it remains only to show that p is identified with p when transported along this equality f=f.Since the type of p is f(𝖭)=b0, this means essentially that when p is composed on the left with the inversePlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath of the equality (6.5.5), it becomes p.But this is obvious, since (6.5.5) is just p itself, while p is reflexivityMathworldPlanetmath.

On the other side, suppose given (g,q).By passing back and forth we obtain (g,q) with

g(a)=𝗋𝖾𝖿𝗅b0-1\\centerdotg(a)\\centerdotg(a0)-1\\centerdot𝗋𝖾𝖿𝗅b0
=g(a)\\centerdotg(a0)-1
=g(a)

using q:g(a0)=𝗋𝖾𝖿𝗅b0 in the last equality.Thus, g=g by function extensionality, so it remains to show that when transported along this equality q is identified with q.At a0, the induced equality g(a0)=g(a0) consists essentially of q itself, while the definition of q involves only canceling inverses and reflexivities.Thus, some tedious manipulations of naturality finish the proof.∎

In particular, for the spheres defined as in (6.5.2) we have

𝖬𝖺𝗉*(𝕊n,B)𝖬𝖺𝗉*(𝕊n-1,ΩB)𝖬𝖺𝗉*(𝟐,ΩnB)ΩnB.

Thus, these spheres 𝕊n have the universal property that we would expect from the spheres defined directly in terms of n-fold loop spaces as in §6.4 (http://planetmath.org/64circlesandspheres).

随便看

 

数学辞典收录了18232条数学词条,基本涵盖了常用数学知识及数学英语单词词组的翻译及用法,是数学学习的有利工具。

 

Copyright © 2000-2023 Newdu.com.com All Rights Reserved
更新时间:2025/5/4 15:59:54