De Bruijn–Erdős theorem
\\PMlinkescapephrase
finite plane
De Bruijn–Erdős theorem
Let be a set of ‘points’, say , andlet , , … be different subsetsof of which any two have exactly one point in common. Now the De Bruijn–Erdős theorem says that , and that if then (up to renumbering) at least one of the following three must be true:
- •
for , and
- •
for , and
- •
is of the form , each contains points,and each point is contained in of the
and we recognise the last case as http://planetmath.org/node/6943finite projective planes of order . For () the first and last case overlap, and for () the last two cases do. The second case is also known as a near-pencil. The last two cases together are examples of linear spaces.
To exclude the first two cases one usually defines projective planes to satisfy some non-triviality conditions; unfortunately that also excludes projective planes of order 0 and 1.
The formulation above was found in the literature [Cam94]. Naturally, ifthe are points we tend to interpret the subsets as lines. However, interpreted in this way the condition that every two share an says rather more than is needed for the structure tobe a finite plane (http://planetmath.org/node/3509linear space) as it insists that no two lines are parallel. The absence of the dual condition, for two to share a , actually means we have too little for the structure to be a finite plane (linear space), as for two points we may not have a line through them. And indeed, while the second and third cases are finite planes without parallel lines, the first case is not a plane.
Erdős–De Bruijn theorem
A dual formulation (which we could whimsically call the Erdős–DeBruijn Theorem) remedies both under- and over-specification for a plane.Indeed, the conditions are now exactly tailored to make the structure a finiteplane (with some parallel lines in the first of the three cases).
Let be a set of ‘points’, say , and let , , … be subsets of (‘lines’) such that for any two points there is a unique that containsthem both. We must now be careful about the points (the former lines) being“different” (this was easier to formulate in the previous version, in whichform it was a simple incidence structure): this condition now takes theform that no two points must have the same collection of lines that areincident with them. Then , and if then (up to renumbering)at least one of the following three must be true:
- •
for , and
- •
for , and
- •
is of the form , each contains points,and each point is contained in of the
For a proof of the theorem (in the former version) see e.g. Cameron [Cam94].
References
- 1
- Cam94 Peter J. Cameron,Combinatorics: topics, techniques, algorithms,
Camb. Univ. Pr. 1994, ISBN 0 521 45761 0
http://www.maths.qmul.ac.uk/ pjc/comb/http://www.maths.qmul.ac.uk/ pjc/comb/(solutions, errata &c.)