proof of pseudoparadox in measure theory
Since this paradox depends crucially on the axiom of choice
, we willplace the application of this controversial axiom at the head of theproof rather than bury it deep within the bowels of the argument.
One can define an equivalence relation on by thecondition that if and only if is rational. Bythe Archimedean property of the real line, for every there will exist a number such that .Therefore, by the axiom of choice, there will exist a choicefunction such that ifand only if .
We shall use our choice function to exhibit a bijection between and . Let be the “wrap-around function” whichis defined as when and when . Define by
From the definition, it is clear that, since and , . Also, it is easy to see that maps into . If , then . On the other hand, if , then . Since is strictly negative, . Since, .
Next, we will show that is injective. Suppose that and . By what we already observed, , so is a non-negative rational number
and . There are 3possible cases: 1) In this case, implies that , which would imply that . 2) In this case, implies which, in turn, implies that , whichis impossible if both and belong to . 3) In this case, implies that , which would imply that . The only remainingpossibility is that , so implies that .
Next, we show that is surjective. Pick a number in .We need to find a number such that .If , we can choose . If , we can choose .
Having shown that is a bijection between and , weshall now complete the proof by examining the action of . As wealready noted, is a rational number. Since the rationalnumbers are countable
, we can arrange them in a series such that no number is counted twice. Define as
It is obvious from this definition that the are mutuallydisjoint. Furthermore, and where is the translate of by .