请输入您要查询的字词:

 

单词 104ClassicalWellorderings
释义

10.4 Classical well-orderings


We now show the equivalence of our ordinalsMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmath with the more familiar classical well-orderings.

Lemma 10.4.1.

Assuming excluded middle, every ordinal is trichotomous:

(a,b:A).(a<b)(a=b)(b<a).
Proof.

By inductionMathworldPlanetmath on a, we may assume that for every a<a and every b:A, we have (a<b)(a=b)(b<a).Now by induction on b, we may assume that for every b<b, we have (a<b)(a=b)(b<a).

By excluded middle, either there merely exists a b<b such that a<b, or there merely exists a b<b such that a=b, or for every b<b we have b<a.In the first case, merely a<b by transitivity, hence a<b as it is a mere proposition.Similarly, in the second case, a<b by transport.Thus, suppose (b:A).(b<b)(b<a).

Now analogously, either there merely exists a<a such that b<a, or there merely exists a<a such that a=b, or for every a<a we have a<b.In the first and second cases, b<a, so we may suppose (a:A).(a<a)(a<b).However, by extensionality, our two suppositions now imply a=b.∎

Lemma 10.4.2.

A well-founded relation contains no cycles, i.e.

(n:).(a:nA).¬((a0<a1)(an-1<an)(an<a0)).
Proof.

We prove by induction on a:A that there is no cycle containing a.Thus, suppose by induction that for all a<a, there is no cycle containing a.But in any cycle containing a, there is some element less than a and contained in the same cycle.∎

In particular, a well-founded relation must be irreflexiveMathworldPlanetmath, i.e. ¬(a<a) for all a.

Theorem 10.4.3.

Assuming excluded middle, (A,<) is an ordinal if and only if every nonempty subset BA has a least element.

Proof.

If A is an ordinal, then by \\autorefthm:wfmin every nonempty subset merely has a minimal element.But trichotomy implies that any minimal element is a least element.Moreover, least elements are unique when they exist, so merely having one is as good as having one.

Conversely, if every nonempty subset has a least element, then by \\autorefthm:wfmin, A is well-founded.We also have trichotomy, since for any a,b the subset\\setofa,b:\\setofx:A|x=ax=bmerely has a least element, which must be either a or b.This implies transitivity, since if a<b and b<c, then either a=c or c<a would produce a cycle.Similarly, it implies extensionality, for if (c:A).(c<a)(c<b), then a<b implies (letting c be a) that a<a, which is a cycle, and similarly if b<a; hence a=b.∎

In classical mathematics, the characterization of \\autorefthm:wellorder is taken as the definition of a well-ordering, with the ordinals being a canonical set of representatives of isomorphism classes for well-orderings.In our context, the structureMathworldPlanetmath identityPlanetmathPlanetmath principle means that there is no need to look for such representatives: any well-ordering is as good as any other.

We now move on to consider consequences of the axiom of choiceMathworldPlanetmath.For any set X, let 𝒫+(X) denote the type of merely inhabited subsets of X:

𝒫+(X):\\setofY:𝒫(X)|(x:X).xY.

Assuming excluded middle, this is equivalently the type of nonempty subsets of X, and we have 𝒫(X)(𝒫+(X))+𝟏.

Theorem 10.4.4.

Assuming excluded middle, the following are equivalentMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath.

  1. 1.

    For every set X, there merely exists a functionf:𝒫+(X)Xsuch that f(Y)Y for all Y:𝒫(X).

  2. 2.

    Every set merely admits the structure of an ordinal.

Of course, 1 is a standard classical version of the axiom of choice; see \\autorefex:choice-function.

Proof.

One direction is easy: suppose 2.Since we aim to prove the mere proposition 1, we may assume A is an ordinal.But then we can define f(B) to be the least element of B.

Now suppose 1.As before, since 2 is a mere proposition, we may assume given such an f.We extend f to a function

f¯:𝒫(X)(𝒫+(X))+𝟏X+𝟏

in the obvious way.Now for any ordinal A, we can define gA:AX+𝟏 by well-founded recursion:

gA(a):f¯(X\\setofgA(b)|(b<a)(gA(b)X))

(regarding X as a subset of X+𝟏 in the obvious way).

Let A:\\setofa:A|gA(a)X be the preimageMathworldPlanetmath of XX+𝟏; then we claim the restrictionPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath gA:AX is injectivePlanetmathPlanetmath.For if a,a:A with aa, then by trichotomy and without loss of generality, we may assume a<a.Thus gA(a)\\setofgA(b)|b<a, so since f(Y)Y for all Y we have gA(a)gA(a).

Moreover, A is an initial segment of A.For gA(a) lies in 𝟏 if and only if \\setofgA(b)|b<a=X, and if this holds then it also holds for any a>a.Thus, A is itself an ordinal.

Finally, since 𝖮𝗋𝖽 is an ordinal, we can take A:𝖮𝗋𝖽.Let X be the image of g𝖮𝗋𝖽:𝖮𝗋𝖽X; then the inversePlanetmathPlanetmath of g𝖮𝗋𝖽 yields an injection H:X𝖮𝗋𝖽.By \\autorefthm:ordunion, there is an ordinal C such that HxC for all x:X.Then by \\autorefthm:ordsucc, there is a further ordinal D such that C<D, hence Hx<D for all x:X.Now we have

g𝖮𝗋𝖽(D)=f¯(X\\setofg𝖮𝗋𝖽(B)|B<D(g𝖮𝗋𝖽(B)X))
=f¯(X\\setofg𝖮𝗋𝖽(B)|g𝖮𝗋𝖽(B)X)

since if B:𝖮𝗋𝖽 and (g𝖮𝗋𝖽(B)X), then B=Hx for some x:X, hence B<D.Now if

\\setofg𝖮𝗋𝖽(B)|g𝖮𝗋𝖽(B)X

is not all of X, then g𝖮𝗋𝖽(D) would lie in X but not in this subset, which would be a contradictionMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmath since D is itself a potential value for B.So this set must be all of X, and hence g𝖮𝗋𝖽 is surjective as well as injective.Thus, we can transport the ordinal structure on 𝖮𝗋𝖽 to X.∎

Remark 10.4.5.

If we had given the wrong proof of \\autorefthm:ordsucc or \\autorefthm:ordunion, then the resulting proof of \\autorefthm:wop would be invalid: there would be no way to consistently assign universePlanetmathPlanetmath levels.As it is, we require propositional resizing (which follows from LEM) to ensure that X lives in the same universe as X (up to equivalence).

Corollary 10.4.6.

Assuming the axiom of choice, the function Ord\\set (which forgets the order structure) is a surjection.

Note that 𝖮𝗋𝖽 is a set, while \\setis a 1-type.In general, there is no reason for a 1-type to admit any surjective function from a set.Even the axiom of choice does not appear to imply that every 1-type does so (although see \\autorefex:acnm-surjset), but it readily implies that this is so for 1-types constructed out of \\set, such as the types of objects of categories of structures as in \\autorefsec:sip.The following corollary also applies to such categories.

Corollary 10.4.7.

Assuming AC, Set admits a weak equivalenceMathworldPlanetmath functor from a strict category.

Proof.

Let X0:𝖮𝗋𝖽, and for A,B:X0 let homX(A,B):(AB).Then X is a strict category, since 𝖮𝗋𝖽 is a set, and the above surjection X0\\set extends to a weak equivalence functor X𝒮et.∎

Now recall from \\autorefsec:cardinals that we have a further surjection |¯|0:\\set𝖢𝖺𝗋𝖽, and hence a composite surjection 𝖮𝗋𝖽𝖢𝖺𝗋𝖽 which sends each ordinal to its cardinality.

Theorem 10.4.8.

Assuming AC, the surjection OrdCard has a sectionPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath.

Proof.

There is an easy and wrong proof of this: since 𝖮𝗋𝖽 and 𝖢𝖺𝗋𝖽 are both sets, 𝖠𝖢 implies that any surjection between them merely has a section.However, we actually have a canonical specified section: because 𝖮𝗋𝖽 is an ordinal, every nonempty subset of it has a uniquely specified least element.Thus, we can map each cardinal to the least element in the corresponding fiber.∎

It is traditional in set theoryMathworldPlanetmath to identify cardinals with their image in 𝖮𝗋𝖽: the least ordinal having that cardinality.

It follows that 𝖢𝖺𝗋𝖽 also canonically admits the structure of an ordinal: in fact, one isomorphicPlanetmathPlanetmath to 𝖮𝗋𝖽.Specifically, we define by well-founded recursion a function :𝖮𝗋𝖽𝖮𝗋𝖽, such that (A) is the least ordinal having cardinality greater than (A/a) for all a:A.Then (assuming 𝖠𝖢) the image of is exactly the image of 𝖢𝖺𝗋𝖽.

随便看

 

数学辞典收录了18232条数学词条,基本涵盖了常用数学知识及数学英语单词词组的翻译及用法,是数学学习的有利工具。

 

Copyright © 2000-2023 Newdu.com.com All Rights Reserved
更新时间:2025/5/4 17:12:35