canonical ordering on pairs of ordinals
The lexicographic ordering on OnOn, the class of all pairs of ordinals, is a well-order in the broad sense, in that every subclass of OnOn has a least element, as proposition
2 of the parent entry readily shows. However, with this type of ordering
, we get initial segments which are not sets. For example, the initial segment of consists of all ordinal pairs of the form , where On, and is easily seen to be a proper class. So the questions is: is there a way to order OnOn such that every initial segment of OnOn is a set? The answer is yes. The construction of such a well-ordering in the following discussion is what is known as the canonical well-ordering of OnOn.
To begin, let us consider a strictly linearly ordered set . We construct a binary relation on as follows:
For example, consider the usual ordering on . Given . Suppose . Then the set of all such that is the union of the three pairwise disjoint sets .
Proposition 1.
. is a strict linear ordering on .
Proof.
It is irreflexive because is never comparable
with itself. It is linear because, first of all, given , exactly one of the three conditions is true, and hence either , or . It remains to show that is transitive
, suppose and .
The two cases
- 1.
and ,
- 2.
and ,
produce . Now, assume , which result in three more cases
- 1.
and ,
- 2.
and ,
- 3.
, and and ,
the first two produce , and the last and . In all cases, we get .∎
Proposition 2.
If is a well-order on , then so is on .
Proof.
Let be non-empty. Let
Then , and therefore has a least element , since is a well-order on . Next, let
Then , and has a least element . Finally, let
Again, , so has a least element . So . We want to show that is the least element of .
Pick any distinct from . Then is at least . If , then . Otherwise, , so that is at least . If , then again we have . But if , then , so that . Since , and , . Therefore , and as a result.∎
The ordering relation above can be generalized to arbitrary classes. Since On is well-ordered by , the canonical ordering on OnOn is a well-ordering by proposition 2. Moreover,
Proposition 3.
Given the canonical ordering on OnOn, every initial segment is a set.
Proof.
Given ordinals On, suppose . The initial segment of is the union of the following collections
- 1.
, which is a subcollection of ,
- 2.
, which again is a subcollection , and
- 3.
, which is a subcollection of .
Since and are both sets, so is the initial segment of .∎
Remark. The canonical well-ordering on OnOn can be used to prove a well-known property of alephs: , for any ordinal .